1.
It is hard to overestimate the pace at which law practice has been changing
in recent decades in response to economic, technological, and cultural
developments. See, e.g., Gary A. Munneke, Seize the Future: Forecasting
and Influencing the Future of the Legal Profession 6-8 (2000). Hard, but
not impossible. Perhaps prompted by the new millennium, an ABA report asserted
in 2001 that "we are in the midst of the biggest transformation of
civilization since the caveman began bartering[, and t]he practice of law
and the administration of justice are at the brink of change of an unprecedented...
magnitude." Comm. on Research About the Future of the Legal Profession,
Am. Bar Ass'n, Working Notes: Deliberations on the Current Status of the
Legal Profession 2 (Aug. 31, 2001), available at http://www.abanet.org/lawfutures/report2001/report_
intro.pdf. RETURN TO TEXT
2.
Stu Webb, Collaborative Law: An Alternative for Attorneys Suffering
"Family Law Burnout," 18 Matrim. Strategist 7 (2000). RETURN TO TEXT
3.
For signs that the use of CL in family law practice is growing rapidly,
See infra notes 10-11. This Article focuses on the use of CL in
divorce cases, but family lawyers have also used it in negotiating pre-nuptial
agreements, structuring non-marital domestic partnerships and breakups,
and resolving child custody disputes. See Pauline H. Tesler, Collaborative
Law: A New Paradigm for Divorce Lawyers, 5 Psychol. Pub. Pol'y &
L. 967, 967 n.2 (1999). As used in divorce, CL is sometimes called Collaborative
Divorce, but this Article avoids that term because it is also used to describe
a process in which a team of mental health and financial professionals
works with divorcing couples. See id. at 978 n.25. Proponents claim
that CL can also be useful for resolving non-family disputes, but there
are reasons to doubt that it will be widely used in other fields. See
Scott R. Peppet, Lawyers Bargaining Ethics, Contract and Collaboration:
The End of the Legal Profession and the Beginning of Professional Pluralism,
90 Iowa L. Rev. 475, 490-92 (2004). First, CL will be unattractive to lawyers
and clients alike unless each side knows enough about the other party and
its lawyer to trust them in collaborative negotiations. Id. at 490.
Second, CL is unlikely to be used in legal disputes in which one party
is represented by a contingent-fee lawyer, because the other side could
jeopardize that lawyer's fee by refusing to settle. Id. at 490-91.
Third, most divorcing spouses are one-shot clients, but law firms would
be reluctant to recommend CL for disputes involving their repeat clients,
fearing that if the process failed and their clients had to find litigation
counsel elsewhere, they might not come back. Id. at 491. Finally,
while divorce clients often know at the outset that they want to avoid
litigation, parties in business disputes are often unsure whether settlement
is preferable until suit is filed and they can determine the strength of
their positions through formal discovery. Id. at 492. RETURN TO TEXT
4.
E.g., Pauline H. Tesler, Collaborative Law: Achieving Effective
Resolution In Divorce Without Litigation 27-28, 52 (2001); Christopher
M. Fairman, Ethics and Collaborative Lawyering: Why Put Old Hats on
New Heads?, 18 Ohio St. J. on Disp. Resol. 505, 522-24 (2003). RETURN TO TEXT
5.
See infra notes 23-50 and accompanying text (providing further description
of the CL process). Under the terms of the agreement, lawyers representing
the spouses in the CL process, and other lawyers in their firms, will be
disqualified. RETURN TO TEXT
6.
Divorce mediation has been widely used for some time. CL, mediation, and
arbitration are often called alternative dispute resolution ("ADR")
processes, but lawyers who participate in those processes dislike that
term because it suggests that litigation is and will remain the dominant
process for resolving legal disputes. See, e.g., Tesler, supra
note 4, at 163 & n.4 (observing a national movement in family law and
civil law generally toward "so-called "alternate' dispute resolution
as the first and favored resort, rather than litigation" (emphasis
added)). RETURN TO TEXT
7.
For representative articles critical of CL, see Penelope Eileen Bryan,
"Collaborative Divorce": Meaningful Reform or Another Quick
Fix?, 5 Psychol. Pub. Pol'y & L. 1001 (1999); Larry R. Spain, Collaborative
Law: A Critical Reflection on Whether a Collaborative Orientation Can Be
Ethically Incorporated into the Practice of Law, 56 Baylor L. Rev.
141 (2004); Gary M. Young, Malpractice Risks of Collaborative Divorce,
Wis. Law., May 2002, available at http://www.wisbar.org/am/?template.cfm??section=?wisconsin_
lawyer?&template=/cm/contentdisplay.cfm&contentid=49 505#z. For
favorable articles by CL pioneers, see Tesler, supra note 3 and
Webb, supra note 2. For a balanced assessment of CL based on an
empirical study, see Julie Macfarlane, Experiences of Collaborative
Law: Preliminary Results from the Collaborative Lawyering Research Project,
2004 J. Disp. Resol. 179. RETURN TO TEXT
8.
See, E.g., Tesler, supra note 4, at 15 ("adversarial
representation"), 19 n.11 ("court-based" practice). RETURN TO TEXT
9.
By the "mainstream bar," I mean the American Bar Association
("ABA") and the state and local bar associations that began to
form in the late nineteenth century. On their origins, early membership
policies, and early activities, see James Willard Hurst, The Growth of
American Law: The Law Makers 285-94 (1950). In addition to the mainstream
bar, there are now more than 1,000 "specialty" bar associations
in the U.S., many of recent origin. Unlike mainstream associations, these
associations are not designed for lawyers generally or for all those practicing
in a particular locale, but rather for lawyers who have a specialty, limited
clientele, practice forum, or work setting in common. Because they are
organized on functional grounds, specialty bars are often more cohesive
than today's mainstream associations. See Judith Kilpatrick, Specialty
Lawyer Associations: Their Role in the Socialization Process, 33 Gonz.
L. Rev. 501, 508 (1997-1998). In that respect, although both specialty
and mainstream bars are only open to lawyers, the former have more in common
than the latter with the new inter-professional CL associations, whose
members all participate in the CL process. The ABA and many state and local
bar associations have made their peace with the relentless growth of specialization
in law practice by forming "sections" dedicated to fields such
as litigation, tax, business law, criminal law, family law, torts and insurance,
and dispute resolution. The ABA's Family Law and Dispute Resolution sections
have taken an interest in CL. See infra notes 166-169 and accompanying
text. RETURN TO TEXT
10.
Formed in 1999, the IACP is the umbrella organization for the CL Movement.
Many members are lawyers but some are mental health providers, appraisers,
accountants, financial planners, or other professionals who serve as neutral
experts in the CL process. A modest fraction of the IACP's membership practices
in Canada or abroad. The IACP had fewer than 100 members in 1999, but more
than 1,000 by 2004. IACP, IACP History, http://www.collaborativepractice.com/?_t.asp?M=3&MS=
3&T=New-History (last visited Dec. 30, 2007). Current membership stands
at more than 3,000, but roughly 15,000 lawyers have had CL training. Telephone
Interview with Pauline Tesler (Oct. 17, 2007). Ms. Tesler is a prominent
CL practitioner in northern California, a founder of the IACP, and a leader
in the CL Movement. RETURN TO TEXT
11.
Local or regional CL practice groups, many of which also accept both lawyers
and other CL professionals as members, have increased from 16 in 1999 to
approximately 175 today. Some require their members to belong to the IACP
as well. Telephone Interview with Pauline Tesler, supra note 10.
A list of the groups, with access to their websites, can be found at IACP,
Collaborative Practice Groups, http://collaborativepractice.com/_t.asp?M=7&T=PracticeGroups
(last visited Dec. 30, 2007). As these numbers suggest, use of CL in divorce
cases is growing apace. According to the only extensive empirical study
to date, CL's "exponential growth... is one of the most significant
developments in the provision of family legal services in the last 25 years."
Julie Macfarlane, The Emerging Phenomenon of Collaborative Family Law (CFL):
A Qualitative Study of CFL Cases vii (2005), available at http://www.justice.gc.ca/?en/?ps/?pad/?reports/2005-FCY-1/2005-FCY-1.pdf
(report to Canada's Department of Justice); see also David A. Hoffman,
A Healing Approach to the Law, Christian Sci. Monitor, Oct. 9, 2007, available
at http://www.csmonitor.com/?2007/?1009/p09s01-coop.html (reporting
that "tens of thousands of divorces" have already been resolved
in CL proceedings). RETURN TO TEXT
12.
See Tesler, supra note 4, at 12-13 (stating that "lawyers often
come to [CL] from the ranks of the most seasoned family lawyers").
RETURN TO TEXT
13.
See Macfarlane, supra note 7, at 180. RETURN TO TEXT
14.
Tesler, supra note 4, at 2. Based on interviews of collaborative
lawyers in several locales, Professor Macfarlane observes that "the
intensity of the revulsion [for traditional divorce practice that they]
expressed... is sometimes startling." Macfarlane, supra note
7, at 190-91. Noting, however, that "almost all [CL] groups articulate
their mission [solely] in terms of enhanced client service," Macfarlane
expresses concern that CL lawyers may be "conflating" their "personal
goals... and the benefits [of CL] for their clients." Id. at
191. It is not clear whether collaborative lawyers who developed an aversion
to divorce litigation before entering the field believe that divorce litigation
is inherently counterproductive or instead that the problem lies in the
current culture of civil litigation. Data from an early study suggest that
the culture of court-based divorce has become much more contentious since
the 1960s. See Hubert J. O'Gorman, Lawyers and Matrimonial Cases: A Study
of Informal Pressures In Private Professional Practice 132-43 (1963) (contrasting
the divorce lawyer's role as counselor and as advocate). Nearly two-thirds
of the lawyers studied identified themselves as "counselors"
who try to "ascertain the nature of the client's problem and then
to work toward a solution that is fair to both spouses." Id.
at 132. RETURN TO TEXT
15.
See Macfarlane, supra note 7, at 191-92 (summarizing interviews
of collaborative lawyers). RETURN TO TEXT
16.
John V. McShane, Foreword to Tesler, supra note 4, at xiv.
RETURN TO TEXT
17.
Id. at xiii (observing that outcomes unfair to one spouse are
common in divorce mediation in which spouses are unrepresented, while court-annexed
mediations in which lawyers participate are little more than a "subpart
to the litigation process"). RETURN TO TEXT
18.
Id. at xiv-xv. Although some family lawyers accept only CL cases
and more would probably like to do so, the supply of collaborative lawyers
in many locales currently outstrips demand and most continue to accept
traditional divorce cases. See Macfarlane, supra note 7, at 193-94.
RETURN TO TEXT
19.
Tesler, supra note 4, at 2. RETURN TO TEXT
20.
Sharon Lerman, Litigants Without Lawyers Flood Courts, Cal. B.J.,
July 2001, at 1 (reporting on a 1997 study finding that more than half
the parties in family law matters appeared in court without an attorney);
Tesler, supra note 4, at 2 (stating that for these reasons divorcing
spouses are "turning away from family law professionals in record
numbers [and] clogging the courts"). RETURN TO TEXT
21.
Divorce lawyers today generally charge hourly fees. Tesler estimates that
CL representation on average costs divorce clients no more than one-tenth
the cost of court-based representation involving litigation, where the
lion's share of the legal fees are for time spent in the litigation itself.
Tesler, supra note 4, at 233. This estimate may be accurate for
the many CL proceedings that produce agreements. See Pauline H. Tesler,
Collaborative Law Neutrals Produce Better Resolutions, 21 Alternatives
to High Cost Litig. 1, 12 (2003) (citing anecdotal reports that more than
95% of CL cases settle). But cf. Collaborative Divorces Kinder,
Gentler, Ariz. Daily Star (Tucson), Dec. 19, 2007, at 21 (reporting
on a study of 199 recent divorce cases by the Boston Law Collaborative.
The study found that divorce mediation, CL, and court-based divorces all
had high settlement rates and that the median cost of mediation, CL, court-based
divorce cases that settled, and cases culminating in "full-blown"
litigation were $ 6,600, $ 19,723, $ 26,830, and $ 77,746, respectively).
Of course, when CL fails and spouses want representation in the ensuing
proceedings, they must retain new lawyers and pay them to "get up
to speed." RETURN TO TEXT
22.
See Tesler, supra note 3, at 972 (citing these and other
reasons why couples choose CL). On the privacy point, in most states all
evidence in court proceedings, including financial disclosure statements,
are matters of public record unless sealed by court order. Tesler, supra
note 4, at 8 n.1. Couples hoping to avoid publicity can also use mediation,
but many reject that alternative for the following reasons: mediators,
as neutrals, cannot give either spouse legal advice or do much to redress
imbalances in spousal sophistication; mediators in most states are unlicensed;
in some mediation models any lawyers who are retained neither attend mediation
sessions nor review settlement terms until they have been negotiated; and,
terms agreed to in mediation without lawyers are vulnerable to legal challenge.
Tesler, supra note 3, at 973-74. Tesler believes that family lawyers
who recognized the limits of mediation developed CL as the "next-generation
family law dispute resolution mode." Tesler, supra note 4,
at 3. RETURN TO TEXT
23.
Tesler, supra note 4. Tesler emphasizes that CL requires lawyers
with special skills in guiding negotiations and managing conflict, that
study and training are necessary to attain those skills, id. at 230-31,
and that collaborative lawyers are not just people "who agree to "behave
nicely.'" Id. at 231. Because Tesler's manual is designed to
pass on to other lawyers what she has learned about "how to do [CL]
well," id. at xxii, its statements are not so much descriptions of
how collaborative lawyers think and act as they are claims about how an
ideal collaborative lawyer would think and act in view of the structure
and aims of the CL process. RETURN TO TEXT
24.
One such document is the Collaborative Law Retainer Agreement ("CLRA"),
the basic contract between lawyer and client. Id. at 121-22. For
a sample, see id. at 137-42 (laying out the lawyer's duties, explaining
the limited scope of the engagement, setting out the lawyer's fee and payment
policies, and advising the client of the key differences between collaborative
and adversarial legal proceedings, including the points that CL lawyers
and clients must be committed to good faith bargaining and voluntary disclosure
of all relevant information and that, to maintain the integrity of the
CL process, the lawyer will withdraw or terminate the process if in her
judgment the client is abusing it). In their first meeting with both clients,
the lawyers review two other documents, called "participation"
agreements, and both spouses sign them. The "Principles and Guidelines
for the Practice of Collaborative Law" describes CL in plain English
and sets out the undertakings of the participants. Id. at 122. For
a sample, see id. at 143-45. The "Stipulation and Order re: Collaborative
Law" restates the parties' commitments and the CL ground rules, including
the lawyer's disqualification agreement, and may also provide that if an
apparent impasse appears the matter may be sent to a private third-party
neutral to see if the collaboration can be salvaged. The Stipulation can
be filed in court if a pro forma divorce petition and response are filed,
but collaboration may also begin without a petition being filed. If filed,
the Stipulation is often signed by a judge and may become a court order,
which may ensure that if litigation ensues the court will not view the
lawyers as attorneys of record. Id at 122-23. For a sample stipulation,
see id. at 146-51. RETURN TO TEXT
25.
Id. at 7. RETURN TO TEXT
26.
Id. at 8. RETURN TO TEXT
27.
Id. Paragraph 9 of Tesler's sample Stipulation and Order purports
to make "notes, work papers, summaries and reports" created in
the CL process inadmissible in any ensuing litigation unless the parties
agree otherwise. Id. at 148-49. This is no guarantee of inadmissibility,
but the materials may be inadmissible under state law that makes communications
in ADR proceedings inadmissible, as a Texas statute expressly provides.
Tex. Fam. Code Ann. § 6.603(h) (Vernon Supp. 2006) (for divorce cases);
see also id. § 153.0072 (Vernon 2002 & Supp. 2007) (providing
like protection for CL proceedings affecting "the parent-child relationship").
RETURN TO TEXT
28.
Tesler, supra note 4, at 8. RETURN TO TEXT
29.
Id. RETURN TO TEXT
30.
Id. "Relevant information" is generally defined as information
that the other side would consider material to the negotiations. That would
presumably include acknowledgements of marital infidelities in some cases
but not others. Comparable disclosure duties now exist in some states for
divorce litigation. See, e.g., Colo. R. Civ. P. 16.2(e)(1) (providing
that parties to domestic relations cases "owe each other and the court
a duty of full and honest disclosure of all facts that materially affect
their rights and interests and those of the children involved in the case").
RETURN TO TEXT
31.
Tesler, supra note 4, at 144 ("Participation with Integrity"
provision in Tesler's "Principles and Guidelines"). By contrast,
the prevailing rules of legal ethics do not generally require corrective
action. See Model Rules of Prof'l Conduct R. 4.1 cmt. 1 (stating that a
lawyer "generally has no affirmative duty to inform an opposing party
of relevant facts"). Wisconsin attorney Gary Young posits that if
the wife's lawyer in a collaboration learns that the husband wants certain
property in his column because his lawyer told him the property could be
sold with no adverse tax consequences, and if the wife's lawyer knows the
advice is incorrect, he must disclose the error, even if the wife believes
disclosure is adverse to her interests. Young, supra note 7. Presumably,
if the wife forbids disclosure, thereby violating the CL ground rules,
the lawyer would have to withdraw. RETURN TO TEXT
32.
Under the heading "Abuse of the Collaborative Process," Tesler's
"Principles and Guidelines" state that the lawyer "will
withdraw from the case and/or will terminate the... process as soon as
possible upon learning that his or her client has withheld or misrepresented
information or otherwise acted so as to undermine or take unfair advantage
of the collaborative law process." Tesler, supra note 4, at
145. Abuses include "the secret disposition" of property, "failing
to disclose the existence or the true nature of assets and/or obligations,"
and failing to "participate in the spirit" of the process. Id.;
see also id. at 138 (similar provisions in the CLRA). If a lawyer
withdraws before the CL process ends, her client may retain another lawyer
and continue, but not if she "terminates" the process. An obligation
to withdraw if the client fails to "participate in the spirit"
of the process would seem to give the lawyer considerable leverage in trying
to convince the client to adhere to his or her commitments as long as the
process continues. RETURN TO TEXT
33.
See Colo. Bar Ass'n Ethics Comm., Ethics Op. 115 (Feb. 24, 2007), available
at http://www.cobar.org/group/display.cfm?GenID=10159&EntityID
=CETH (stating that as a result of the lawyer's commitment to withdraw
if she concludes that her client is participating in bad faith, "the
lawyer's continued participation serves as an implicit certification of
the client's good faith"). Tesler states that a collaborative lawyer
should be able to rely on her counterpart to ensure that "the information
communicated during the process is as accurate as [that] lawyer can make
it." Tesler, supra note 3, at 990. In view of the need for
mutual trust, she cautions lawyers to be wary of collaborating with a lawyer
who is "an unknown quantity." Id. at 990 n.61. This highlights
a distinctive feature of collaborative law practice. While traditional
divorce lawyers might sometimes decide whether to accept an engagement
by considering who will be representing the other spouse, collaborative
lawyers regard this as an important consideration in all cases because
the ability of the lawyers to trust and cooperate with one another is vital.
RETURN TO TEXT
34.
Under prevailing ethics rules, lawyers may not knowingly assist clients
in perpetrating frauds, but have no general duty to monitor clients for
possible wrongdoing. Model Rules of Prof'l Conduct R. 1.2(d). RETURN TO TEXT
35.
Tesler, supra note 4, at 10. RETURN TO TEXT
36.
Id. at 60-62, 66-67. Tesler notes that collaborative lawyers exchange
a great deal of information that traditional lawyers probably would not
offer. To advance the interests of their client, for example, they might
alert one another to "emotional issues and concerns of their respective
clients that could affect the tone or movement of a four-way meeting."
Id. at 167. The lawyers presumably understand their clients to have
"impliedly authorized" these disclosures. See Model Rules of
Prof'l Conduct R. 1.6(a) (recognizing that a lawyer may disclose confidential
client information when doing so is "impliedly authorized in order
to carry out the representation"). RETURN TO TEXT
37.
Tesler, supra note 3, at 993; see also Tesler, supra note
4, at 85-86 (stating that such modeling enables each client to see other
adults "communicating and reasoning effectively with the spouse").
RETURN TO TEXT
38.
Tesler, supra note 3, at 991. To support her views on this point,
Tesler notes that the American Academy of Matrimonial Lawyers' practice
guidelines, Bounds of Advocacy, as revised in 2000, go "so far as
to advise that a lawyer need not follow even a competent client's irrational
or potentially harmful directives." Tesler, supra note 4, at
162 n.2. RETURN TO TEXT
39.
The "Principles and Guidelines" agreement, see supra note
24, acknowledges the spouses' understanding that "while our collaborative
lawyers share a commitment to the process described in this document, each
of them has a professional duty to represent his or her own client diligently,
and is not the lawyer for the other party"). Tesler, supra
note 4, at 144. RETURN TO TEXT
40.
See id. at 10, 160; Sandra S. Beckwith & Sherri Goren Slovin, The
Collaborative Lawyer as Advocate: A Response, 18 Ohio St. J. on Disp.
Resol 497, 500-01, 503 (2003). But see James K.L. Lawrence, Collaborative
Lawyering: A New Development in Conflict Resolution, 17 Ohio St. J.
on Disp. Resol 431, 439 (2002) (arguing that the collaborative lawyer's
responsibilities place her in a "unique ethical position," somewhere
between a traditional advocate and a neutral); Young, supra note
7 (arguing that under Wisconsin law collaborative lawyers would be understood
to represent both spouses and could be subject tocivil liability or professional
discipline for doing so). RETURN TO TEXT
41.
Tesler, supra note 4, at 70-71. RETURN TO TEXT
42.
Id. at 167. Although CL clients make a commitment at the outset
to provide all relevant documents and information, Tesler recognizes that
consent can be rescinded. She adds, however, that if a client refuses after
consultation to turn over something the collaborative lawyer thinks is
"material," the lawyer must withdraw. Id. Moreover, if
the client's failure to disclose the information after promising to do
so would constitute fraud and be "reasonably certain to result in
substantial injury to the [other party's] financial interests or property,"
the lawyer would be permitted under the Model Rules to disclose it, see
Model Rules of Prof'l Conduct R. 1.6(b)(2), (3), and perhaps required to
do so. Id. at R. 4.1(b) (requiring disclosures permitted under 1.6(b)
if necessary to avoid assisting in the client's fraud). RETURN TO TEXT
43.
Tesler, supra note 4, at 83, 99 (emphasis added). RETURN TO TEXT
44.
Id. at 83 (distinguishing "positional bargaining," which
includes demands that do not reflect a party's real priorities, from "interest-based
bargaining"). By eschewing "positional bargaining," the
collaborative lawyer forgoes using forms of "puffery" in negotiations
that the prevailing rules of legal ethics would permit. See Model Rules
of Prof'l Conduct R. 4.1(a) & cmt. 2 (forbidding lawyers in negotiating
on a client's behalf to make "false statements of material fact,"
but characterizing as immaterial "estimates of price or value placed
on the subject of a transaction and [statements about a client's] intentions
as to an acceptable settlement of a claim"). RETURN TO TEXT
45.
Tesler, supra note 4, at 99-100. RETURN TO TEXT
46.
Id. at 100. Tesler's ideal collaborative lawyer will also separate
a client's "true, long-term interests from emotion-based impulses
and reactions," help the client develop a "more balanced view
of problems and potential solutions," and even challenge the client
to transform his "understanding of what is real and what is not."
Id. at 42. RETURN TO TEXT
47.
Id. at 80. Stressing the importance of the "relational estate"
makes it hard to judge ex post whether a spouse who would probably have
gotten more tangible assets through litigation necessarily got an inferior
result in the collaboration. RETURN TO TEXT
48.
Id. at 81 (emphasis added). Perhaps CL clients do agree to this,
but no such terms routinely appear in the CL documents. Tesler does observe
that when collaborative lawyers bring the shadow client/true client distinction
to a prospective client's attention, it never occurs to the prospective
client to say, "No, I want to make decisions and plan goals and strategies
with you while I am in a shadow state." Id. at 81 n.3. But
this hardly adds up to an explicit lawyer-client agreement. And even if
such agreements are made, one wonders how clients imagine they will play
out. My wife and I briefly considered an experiment in which we would each
point out the judgments we believed the other had reached in a "shadow
state" as Tesler defines it and, after a "cooling-off period,"
would discuss whether in hindsight we concurred with the other's characterizations.
We decided against it for fear the experiment might put us in need of divorce
lawyers. RETURN TO TEXT
49.
Id. at 80. Tesler asserts that the "shadow client" is
the one "most often being represented by conventional divorce lawyers
in the slide toward the courthouse." Id. If this is the case,
one wonders whether conventional divorce lawyers or collaborative lawyers
are really more respectful of client autonomy and how an arbiter would
go about deciding the question. See note 52 infra. RETURN TO TEXT
50.
Id. All this may seem like a serious departure from the bedrock
ethical principle that decisions about the objectives of representation
are for the client to make. See Model Rules of Prof'l Conduct R. 1.2(a)
(stating that a lawyer "shall abide by a client's decisions concerning
the objectives of representation"). But that principle means only
that it is "ultimately" for the client to choose the objectives,
id. at Rule 1.2 cmt. 1 (emphasis added), not that it is improper
for a lawyer to try to influence the client's choices through counseling.
The lawyer qua counselor is required to "render candid advice"
and, in doing so, may refer not only to law, but to moral and prudential
considerations as well. Id. at R.2.1. Professor Macfarlane describes
the collaborative lawyer's role as a "merger of the lawyer's counseling
and advocacy functions," not only in the structure of the process,
in which "advocacy can no longer take the form of the unmodulated
assertion of positions," but also "philosophically." Macfarlane,
supra note 7, at 202. RETURN TO TEXT
51.
For one example, see supra note 44. In addition, a lawyer "generally
has no affirmative duty to inform an opposing party of relevant facts,"
Model Rules of Prof'l Conduct R. 4.1 cmt 1, but the CL agreements call
for information that might otherwise be protected as confidential to be
disclosed whenever necessary in order to correct an inadvertent error by
the other side. See supra note 42 and accompanying text. RETURN TO TEXT
52.
See supra notes 46-50 and accompanying text. To put the active
role CL lawyers play in defining client interests and objectives in perspective,
it is worth noting that litigators are sometimes criticized for imputing
standard objectives to their clients rather than working to identify each
client's true aims. See Warren Lehman, The Pursuit of a Client's Interest,
77 Mich. L. Rev. 1078, 1087 (1979) (criticizing lawyers for too often assuming
that all clients want "more money, freedom from incarceration[,] or
procedural delay"); William H. Simon, The Ideology of Advocacy:
Procedural Justice and Professional Ethics, 1978 Wis. L. Rev. 29, 52-59
(same). RETURN TO TEXT
53.
The term "paradigm shift" entered the lexicon when Thomas
Kuhn famously argued that scientific disciplines are dominated at any given
time by a single conceptual framework or paradigm, and that changes or
advances occur not so much through small increments as through major upheavals,
"revolutions," or "paradigm shifts." Thomas Kuhn, The
Structure of Scientific Revolutions (3d ed. 1996). The term is now used
loosely to refer even to shifts of no great magnitude in any body of thought
or social practice. See Jeffrey W. Stempel, New Paradigm, Normal Science,
or Crumbling Construct? Trends in Adjudicatory Procedure and Litigation
Reform, 59 Brook. L. Rev. 659, 695-705 (1993) (criticizing the popularization
of the term, which has made it a "buzzword"). RETURN TO TEXT
54.
See supra note 4 and accompanying text. RETURN TO TEXT
55.
Tesler, supra note 4, at 3, 163; see also Joan B. Kelly, A Decade
of Divorce Mediation Research, 34 Fam. & Conciliation Ct. Rev.
373 (1996). RETURN TO TEXT
56.
Tesler, supra note 4, at 3; see also supra note 22. RETURN TO TEXT
57.
Tesler, supra note 4, at 21 & n.13 (citing Dennis P. Stolle,
David B. Wexler, & Bruce J. Winick, Practicing Therapeutic Jurisprudence:
Law as a Helping Profession (2000)). Practicing Therapeutic Jurisprudence
is a leading work in the field. RETURN TO TEXT
58.
Tesler, supra note 4, at 163-64 & nn.3, 5. On the unbundling
trend generally, see Forest S. Mosten, Unbundled Legal Services:
A Guide to Delivering Legal Services A La Carte (Am. Bar Ass'n 2000). The
growing acceptance of agreements limiting the scope of representation even
at the risk that clients will later regret the limitation may reflect another
trend -- a growing willingness among judges, ethics rule makers, and rule
interpreters to permit lawyers and clients to "customize" their
relationships through contract, and a corresponding narrowing of rules
and rule interpretations that are designed to protect clients from their
own folly. This trend is discussed in Part II infra. It is unclear how
far the acceptance of customizing lawyer-client relationships through contract
may go, but Scott Peppet recently proposed a radical change whereby lawyers
and clients could choose to have their relationship governed by one of
several alternative sets of ethics rules concerning the degree of candor
with which a lawyer and client will negotiate with another party. Peppet,
supra note 3, at 514-36. RETURN TO TEXT
Finally, CL may appear at
first blush to reflect a trend toward relying on lawyers as client "gatekeepers,"
i.e., monitors or certifiers of their clients' conduct or circumstances.
See John C. Coffee, Jr., The Attorney as Gatekeeper: An Agenda for the
SEC, 103 Colum. L. Rev. 1293 (2003); John C. Coffee, Jr., Understanding
Enron: "It's About the Gatekeepers, Stupid," 57 Bus. Law.
1403, 1405 (2002) [hereinafter Coffee, Understanding Enron] (defining
gatekeepers in the corporate context as "reputational intermediaries
who provide verification and certification services to investors"
and "lend their professional reputations to a transaction");
Reinier H. Kraakman, Gatekeepers: The Anatomy of a Third-Party Enforcement
Strategy, 2 J.L. Econ. & Org. 53 (1986). But a collaborative lawyer's
duty to monitor a client for compliance with her commitments, unlike a
lawyer's duties under the securities laws to monitor a corporate client
for the benefit of the investing public, see Standards of Professional
Conduct for Attorneys Appearing and Practicing Before the Securities and
Exchange Commission in the Representation of an Issuer, 17 C.F.R. §
205.3(b), (d) (2005), stems from the client's ex ante choice to
be monitored in hopes of garnering the other side's trust through lawyer
"certification" of the client's good faith. On the collaborative
lawyer's monitoring duties, see supra notes 36-37 and accompanying
text. RETURN TO TEXT
59.
Tesler, supra note 4, at 27 (using the term "making the paradigm
shift" to describe "the process of unlearning adversarial behaviors
and learning collaborative behaviors"); id. at 4 (stating that
"effective collaborative lawyers exhibit thought processes, attitudes,
and skills entirely different from the armaments of a trial lawyer").
RETURN TO TEXT
60.
Id. at 40. RETURN TO TEXT
61.
Id. at 41. RETURN TO TEXT
62.
Id. at 42. RETURN TO TEXT
63.
Id. at 44. RETURN TO TEXT
64.
Id. at 49. RETURN TO TEXT
65.
Many problems in civil litigation today stem from the fact that litigators
so often find themselves opposite a lawyer they do not know or expect to
deal with regularly in the future, leaving them with little incentive to
stay on their best behavior. See Peppet, supra note 3, at 487 (stating
that "as the profession has expanded... over the last decades, it
has become increasingly common [even] for attorneys within a firm not to
know each other," let alone opposing counsel); see also infra note
175 (noting that the problem of maintaining good faith negotiations between
strangers is a central concern in game theory). RETURN TO TEXT
66.
Tesler asserts that lawyers are socialized into the dominant adversarial
paradigm, Tesler, supra note 4, at 32, not only in conventional
litigation practice but in law school as well. Id. at 24. I have
been a law professor since 1971. Call me biased, but the considerable attention
law schools have been giving for at least three decades to client counseling,
relational contracting, interdisciplinary training, alternative dispute
resolution, and "getting to yes" in negotiations makes me doubt
that we are the culprits. RETURN TO TEXT
67.
Id. at 24 (emphasis added). RETURN TO TEXT
68.
Id. at 16. There is, I recognize, an ambiguity here. Does Tesler
mean only that if the effort to reach an agreement through collaboration
fails and the matter goes to litigation, the lawyers involved will experience
that as a failure, or does she mean that the good collaborative lawyer
will inevitably have a jaundiced view of litigation as a technique for
processing divorces? RETURN TO TEXT
69.
Tesler stresses the importance of gaining a "sophisticated understanding"
of the psychodynamics of divorce and of child development, a working understanding
of "transference and countertransference in the attorney-client relationship
and in marital relationships," familiarity with the full range of
dispute resolution techniques, and knowledge of certain bargaining techniques.
Tesler, supra note 3, at 985. For some of her ideas about the psychology
of divorce clients and how it should bear on the attorney-client relationship,
see supra notes 48-50 and accompanying text. RETURN TO TEXT
70.
See generally Andrew Abbott, The System of Professions (1988)
(arguing that professions change in structure and "jurisdiction"
largely as a result of inter-and intra-professional competition for various
kinds of work). RETURN TO TEXT
71.
See supra note 18. According to the IACP's Ethics Task Force, of
which Tesler is a member, "there are many thousands of CL attorneys
whose practices are a hybrid -- i.e., they take some cases to court and...
handle others on a CL basis." IACP Ethics Task Force, The Ethics
of the Collaborative Participation Agreement: A Critique of Colorado's
Maverick Ethics Opinion, Collaborative Rev., Spring 2006, at 8, 10,
available at http://www.collaborativelaw.us?/articles?/IACP_Critique_
of_Colo_Opinion.pdf. RETURN TO TEXT
72.
See Abbott, supra note 70, at 195 (observing that for emerging professional
groups "new values serve as convenient ideologies" with which
to attract recruits). RETURN TO TEXT
73.
But see Macfarlane, supra note 7, at 181 (stating that among the
many family mediators who are lawyers, "the small number who have
been successful in developing large family mediation practices often abandon
legal practice"). Professor Macfarlane seems to assume that those
who abandon practice do so because they prefer mediation, not because their
mediation work is too time consuming and remunerative to do anything else.
Id. She may also assume that lawyer-mediators who continue to represent
divorce clients would stop if only they could afford to do so. RETURN TO TEXT
74.
John Lande, Possibilities for Collaborative Law: Ethics and Practice
of Lawyer Disqualification and Process Control in a New Model of Lawyering,
64 Ohio St. L.J. 1315, 1317 n.3 (2003). RETURN TO TEXT
75.
Id. at 1328 (suggesting that CL practice could "influence traditional
legal practice, which might be its most significant impact"). Lawyers
who do both CL and traditional divorce work might also be more objective
than "pure" collaborative or traditional divorce lawyers in advising
prospective divorce clients about the pros and cons of both alternatives
and their suitability in any given case. And, there is no evidence that
divorce lawyers with hybrid practices are more exposed than others to malpractice
suits or bar grievances. RETURN TO TEXT
76.
Research suggests that lawyers often belong to several different practice
communities, each with its own, possibly conflicting, negotiating norms
and strategies. See Macfarlane, supra note 7, at 196 (citing Lynn
M. Mather et al., Divorce Lawyers at Work: Varieties of Professionalism
in Practice 41-48 (2001)). RETURN TO TEXT
77.
The lawyer's role as an objective "evaluator" of a client's
legal circumstances for the benefit of others has been recognized in the
prevailing rules of legal ethics for years. An example is the lawyer engaged
by a would-be borrower to prepare a legal opinion for use by a prospective
lender that seeks assurances that the borrower has clean title to the proposed
collateral. See Model Rules of Prof'l Conduct R. 2.3 (describing a lawyer's
duties in providing an evaluation of a client's legal circumstances for
the benefit of third parties). RETURN TO TEXT
78.
See Ted Schneyer, An Interpretation of Recent Developments in the Regulation
of Law Practice, 30 Okla. City U. L. Rev. 559, 570-84 (2005) (discussing
the growing activism of Congress, the Department of Justice, the Treasury
Department, and the SEC in regulating lawyers practicing in fields of special
federal interest). RETURN TO TEXT
79.
The mainstream bar's largely favorable response to CL, discussed below,
may in part reflect the view that legislative and judicial acceptance inevitably
means that the proverbial horse is out of the barn. Without support from
either branch, it is hard to see how a bar campaign to derail the Collaborative
Law Movement could succeed. RETURN TO TEXT
80.
Cal. Fam. Code § 2013 (West 2007); N.C. Gen. Stat. §§50-70
to -79 (2007); Tex. Fam. Code Ann. § 6.603 (Vernon 2006); see also
id. § 153.0072 (Vernon 2002 & Supp. 2007) (authorizing use
of CL in disputes involving parent-child relationships). The California
legislature has also formed a working group to draft procedures to structure
the CL process. See Andrew Schouten, Breaking Up Is No Longer Hard to Do,
38 McGeorge L. Rev. 125, 132 (2007) (discussing the California legislation).
In addition, a recent Utah statute creates a mandatory orientation course
for parties who file for divorce or separation and have children. The course
includes information about the options available for proceeding with a
divorce, and collaborative law is designated as an option. Utah Code Ann.
§ 30-3-11.4 (2007). RETURN TO TEXT
The CL statutes are largely
silent about the lawyer's ethical duties, but recognize lawyer disqualification
agreements as a defining feature of CL. N.C. Gen. Stat. § 50-72; Tex.
Fam. Code Ann.§§6.603(c)(4), 153.0072(c)(4). North Carolina and
Texas also make documents and communications in a CL proceeding inadmissible
in subsequent litigation. N.C. Gen. Stat. § 50-77; Tex. Fam. Code
Ann § 6.603(h). If a divorce petition is filed before the CL process
begins, Texas also provides for a stay of court proceedings pending the
outcome, id. § 6.603(c)(2), and North Carolina provides for
the tolling of all time limits for adjudicating the case while the CL process
is pending. N.C. Gen. Stat. § 50-73. Many state supreme courts construe
their state constitution to grant ultimate authority to regulate law practice
to them. See Restatement (Third) of the Law Governing Lawyers §
1 cmt. c & Rptr's Note (2000). Whether state legislatures have been
largely silent on the ethics of collaborative lawyering in deference to
the traditional primacy of state supreme courts in regulating law practice
is unclear. But see infra note 81. RETURN TO TEXT
81.
National Conference of Commissioners on Uniform State Laws, Collaborative
Law Act (Discussion Draft) (Oct. 2007). The draft treats the four-way disqualification
agreement as a key element of CL. Id. § 2(b)(1)(C) (disqualifying
counsel and any lawyer associated with counsel who represented a Party
in the Collaborative Process from "representing any Party in any proceeding
or matter substantially related to the Dispute"). The draft is silent
on other ethics issues concerning collaborative lawyering, but notes that
lawyers' ethical duties are established by the rules of professional responsibility
enacted in each state by the "institutions that regulate the conduct
of lawyers, such as the judiciary and bar association ethics committees."
Id. at 7 (Prefatory Note). To avoid "inflexibly regulating
a still-developing" process and to "minimize the risk of [separation-of-powers
disputes] between the judicial branch and the legislature in prescribing
the conditions under which attorneys may practice law," the draft
also takes no position on whether special training should be a prerequisite
for CL work. Id. at 9. RETURN TO TEXT
82.
E.g., S.F. (Cal.) Unif. Local Rules of Ct. R. 11.17 (2006); Unif.
Rules for La. Dist. Cts. tit. IV, § 3 (2005); Minn. Sup. Ct. Gen.
R. Practice for the District Courts, R. 111.05 (eff. Jan. 1, 2008) (defining
collaborative law and making CL cases eligible for deferral of scheduling
orders); Utah Code of Jud. Admin. Ch 4, art. 5, R. 40510 (2006); see also
Pauline A. Tesler, Donna J. Hitchens: Family Law Judge for the Twenty-First
Century: How the World's First Superior Court Collaborative Law Department
Came to Be, Collaborative Q., Oct. 2000, at 1 (describing San Francisco
court procedures for CL cases). RETURN TO TEXT
83.
Danny Hakim, Chief Judge Plans Center to Ease Divorce Cases,
N.Y. Times, Feb. 27, 2007. RETURN TO TEXT
84.
See, e.g., Jennifer Jackson, Interview with the Hon. W. Ross
Foote: Collaboration from the Bench, Collaborative Rev. (Judges' Issue),
at 1 (interviewing Louisiana judge "best known to Collaborative Practice
groupies as the guy who got the $ 200,000 grant to build a Collaborative
Practice infrastructure and coalition from the ground up"); Sample
Letter to People Filing for Divorce, id. at 9 (letter from Donna J. Hitchens,
Supervising Judge, San Francisco Unified Family Court, informing divorcing
spouses that "one of the best methods is to work things out by participating
in collaborative law"); Carla W. Newton, Judges See Benefits of
Collaborative Divorce Process, Republican (Holyoke, Mass.), Jan. 31,
2007, available at http://www.masslive.com/?holyokeplus/republican/index.ssf?/base
/news-2/?1170146955313960?.xml?&coll=1. Family court judges may be
attracted to CL in hopes of easing their caseloads, but Tesler reports
that many family court judges are as dissatisfied with adversarial divorce
proceedings as the lawyers who began the Collaborative Law Movement. Telephone
Interview with Pauline Tesler, supra note 10. RETURN TO TEXT
85.
Indeed, lawyers in more than 30 states must be state bar members in order
to practice law. See Theodore J. Schneyer, The Incoherence of the Unified
Bar Concept: Generalizing from the Wisconsin Case, 1983 Am. B. Found.
Res. J. 1, 1-2 n.1. RETURN TO TEXT
86.
On the six-year political process that produced the Model Rules, see
Theodore Schneyer, Professionalism as Politics: The Making of a Modern
Legal Ethics Code, in Lawyers' Ideals/Lawyers' Practices: Transformations
in the American Legal Profession 95-143 (Robert L. Nelson et al. eds.,
1992). The ABA adopted the Canons of Professional Ethics in 1908 and the
Code of Professional Responsibility in 1969. See Restatement (Third) of
the Law Governing Lawyers § 1 cmt. b & Rptr's Note (2000). RETURN TO TEXT
87.
See Lucian T. Pera, Grading ABA Leadership on Legal Ethics Leadership:
State Adoption of the ABA Model Rules of Professional Conduct, 30 Okla.
City U. L. Rev. 637, 640 (2005) (noting that the 1983 Model Rules were
adopted in over 40 states, often with only minor changes). The ABA's extensive
amendments to the Model Rules in 2002 have also been widely adopted in
the states. Id. at 810. Although the ABA and the state bar associations
can only recommend ethics rules to the state supreme courts, the courts
have long treated them as "the preliminary arena of public government"
in which the law of lawyering is "first formulated." Corinne
Lathrop Gilb, Hidden Hierarchies: The Professions and Government 216 (1966).
RETURN TO TEXT
88.
ABA Model Rules for Lawyer Disciplinary Enforcement (2002); ABA Recommendation
for the Evaluation of Disciplinary Enforcement (1992). RETURN TO TEXT
89.
Schneyer, supra note 85, at 22-23. RETURN TO TEXT
90.
See John Lande, Principles for Policymaking About Collaborative
Law and Other ADR Processes, 22 Ohio St. J. Disp. on Resol. 619, 697-99
(2007) (arguing that it is too soon to address collaborative lawyering
in the Model Rules; further CL development is needed before drafting a
fixed and uniform rule). RETURN TO TEXT
91.
Indeed, it was only after years of lobbying that a skeletal provision was
added to the Model Rules recognizing the role lawyers sometimes play as
third-party neutrals. See Douglas H. Yarn, Lawyer Ethics in ADR
and the Recommendation of Ethics 2000 to Revise the Model Rules of Professional
Conduct, 54 Ark. L. Rev. 207 (2001) (providing legislative history
of Model Rule 2.4 on The Lawyer as Third-Party Neutral). At present, legal
scholars are hotly debating the desirability of adding a CL provision to
the Model Rules. Compare Lande, supra note 90, at 697-99 (arguing
against a rule for now), with Christopher M. Fairman, Why We Still Need
a Model Rule for Collaborative Law: A Reply to Professor Lande, 22
Ohio St. J. on Disp. Resol. 707 (2007) (arguing that such a rule is needed
now) and Christopher M. Fairman, A Proposed Model Rule for Collaborative
Law, 21 Ohio St. J. on Disp. Resol. 73, 116-21 (2005). While the debate
is interesting, it seems likely for now to remain a purely academic exercise.
RETURN TO TEXT
92.
See Fred C. Zacharias, Specificity in Professional Responsibility Codes:
Theory, Practice, and the Paradigm of Prosecutorial Ethics, 69 Notre
Dame L. Rev. 223, 224, 300-02 (1993) (finding a modest "drift toward
specificity" in the ABA codes over time but few provisions even now
that explicitly address practice in a specific field). One constraint on
the level of detail in the Model Rules is the notion that the ABA's interest
in maintaining a cohesive legal profession cautions against adorning the
Model Rules with detailed rules for specialized fields of practice as if
the Rules were a "Christmas tree." See id. at 231-39.
The task of developing ethical guidelines or protocols for practice in
specific fields has fallen instead to specialty bar associations, See
infra note 93, and to certain ABA sections. E.g., ABA Section
of Litigation, Ethical Guidelines for Settlement Negotiations (Aug. 2002),
reprinted in Prof'l Responsibility Standards, Rules & Statutes (John
S. Dzienkowski ed.) (unabridged ed. 2007-08); ABA Section of Family Law,
Standards of Practice for Lawyers Representing Children in Custody Cases
(Aug. 2003). Guidelines drafted by ABA sections are expressly not designed
to preempt the Model Rules. RETURN TO TEXT
93.
On the history and interpretive nature of bar association ethics opinions,
see Ted Finman & Theodore Schneyer, The Role of Bar Association
Ethics Opinions in Regulating Lawyer Conduct: A Critique of the Work of
the ABA Committee on Ethics and Professional Responsibility, 29 UCLA
L. Rev. 67, 69-70 n.4 (1981). Ethics opinions, of course, are not the only
source of ethics rule interpretation. An important fact about the evolving
structure of the organized bar is the growing number of specialty bars
that publish detailed guidelines for practice in their field. Those guidelines
often purport to be elaborations on the Model Rules. See, e.g.,
Am. Acad. of Matrimonial Lawyers, The Bounds of Advocacy: Goals for Family
Lawyers, Preliminary Statement (1991) (explaining that the guidelines construe
the Model Rules as they bear on family law practice, and were developed
because members "encountered instances where the [Model Rules] provided
insufficient... guidance"); ACTEC Commentaries on the Model Rules
of Professional Conduct, 28 Real Prop. Prob. & Tr. J. 865 (1994)
(interpreting the Model Rules as they bear on trust and estate practice).
But the "elaborations" sometimes appear to conflict with the
Model Rules. Under the Model Rules, for example, lawyers must permit their
clients to decide the objectives of representation. Model Rules of Prof'l
Conduct R. 1.2(a). Yet the latest version of The Bounds of Advocacy urges
divorce lawyers not to permit clients to contest child custody for "financial
leverage," Am. Acad. of Matrimonial Lawyers, The Bounds of Advocacy
§ 6.2 (2000), but instead to "consider the welfare of, and seek
to minimize the adverse impact of the divorce on, the minor children."
Id. § 6.1. RETURN TO TEXT
94.
It has been argued that bar-association ethics opinions may have "more...
to do with determining the conduct of... lawyers" than the rules they
purport to interpret. Barlow F. Christensen, Group Legal Services 46 (Tentative
Draft 1967). This is probably an overstatement, but ABA ethics opinions
are often cited in disciplinary cases, cases ruling on motions to disqualify
lawyers from litigation, cases resolving fee disputes, cases determining
lawyers' civil liabilities, and cases adjudicating ineffective assistance
of counsel claims. See Finman & Schneyer, supra note 93, at
85-86 (citing cases). Thus, ethics opinions can influence lawyers both
directly and indirectly, through their impact on other authorities. On
the demand for ethics opinions as a source of guidance for lawyers in interpreting
the rules of legal ethics, see id. at 76-77. RETURN TO TEXT
95.
See Hoffman, supra note 11 (claiming that after the Colorado Bar
Association issued an advisory ethics opinion in early 2007 declaring CL
practice unethical, "thousands of lawyers across the United States
who have been using the collaborative law process waited uneasily to see
which way the regulatory winds would blow in their states"). Conversely,
when the ABA ethics committee issued an opinion in August 2007 rejecting
the Colorado Bar Association's analysis and conclusion, Hoffman called
the ABA opinion a "giant step forward" for conflict resolution
in the U.S. Id. RETURN TO TEXT
96.
See Christopher M. Fairman, Growing Pains: Collaborative Law and the
Challenge of Legal Ethics, 30 Campbell L. Rev. (forthcoming 2008) (manuscript
at 17, on file with author) (describing bar association ethics opinions
as "the ultimate check on collaborative law"). RETURN TO TEXT
97.
Tesler, supra note 4, at 31. RETURN TO TEXT
98.
For a stark version of this criticism, see Gerald J. Postema, Moral
Responsibility in Professional Ethics, 55 N.Y.U. L. Rev. 63, 73 (1980)
(claiming that the prevailing rules of legal ethics are built on a Partisanship
principle that commits lawyers to the aggressive and single-minded pursuit
of client objectives "within, but all the way up to, the limits of
the law"). Postema also claims that lawyers' responsibilities are
"entirely predetermined" by the rules of professional conduct.
Id. at 82. Some CL proponents have made more nuanced arguments about
the difficulty of reconciling collaborative lawyering with the "zealous
advocacy" model or "adversarial paradigm" that supposedly
permeates the Model Rules. E.g., Fairman, supra note 4, at
523 (asserting that "ethical rules borrowed from the adversarial model
-- such as [the requirement of] zealous advocacy - seem ill-suited to the
paradigm shift" that CL requires, though it may be possible to "shoehorn"
collaborative practice into "traditional ... ethics codes");
Kimberlee K. Kovach, Lawyer Ethics Must Keep Pace with Practice: Plurality
in Lawyering Roles Demands Diverse and Innovative Ethical Standards,
39 Idaho L. Rev. 399, 402 (2003) (stating that ethical standards are based
"almost exclusively on an adversarial paradigm" and "likely
[to be] inappropriate" for CL); Spain, supra note 7, at 156
(questioning "whether current ethics rules can accommodate this new
collaborative law model" since the Model Rules "of course, are
based on the dominant practice model of an attorney representing a client
as a partisan advocate in a traditional adversarial role"). RETURN TO TEXT
99.
Ky. Bar Ass'n Ethics Comm., Ethics Op. E-425 (2005). RETURN TO TEXT
100.
Letter from Patrick R. Burns, Senior Assistant Dir., Office of Lawyers
Prof'l Responsibility, Minn. Judicial Ctr., to Laurie Savran, Collaborative
Law Inst. (Mar. 12, 1997). RETURN TO TEXT
101.
N.J. Advisory Comm. On Prof'l Ethics, Ethics Op. 699 (2005), 2005 WL 3890576.
The New Jersey committee operates under the auspices of the New Jersey
Supreme Court, rather than the state bar association. RETURN TO TEXT
102.
N.C. St. Bar, Formal Eth. Op.1 (2002). RETURN TO TEXT
103.
Pa. Bar Ass'n Comm. on Legal Ethics & Prof'l Responsibility, Informal
Op. 2004-24 (2004), 2004 WL 2758094 (authored by Professor Laurel S. Terry).
RETURN TO TEXT
104.
See, e.g., id. at 2 (stating that the author was "not prepared
to say that using [a] collaborative law process in a domestic relations
context is a per se violation of the Pennsylvania Rules of Professional
Conduct"; urging lawyers who accept CL cases to "carefully consider"
those rules to ensure compliance in "each lawyer-client relationship
they establish"; and suggesting that if the lawyer seeking the ethics
opinion should find that essential features of CL cannot be reconciled
with the current rules because CL "involves a paradigm shift,"
the lawyer could propose specialized ethics rules on the subject for the
committee to consider); see also N.J. Advisory Comm. on Prof'l Ethics,
Op. 699 (2005), 2005 WL 3890576, at 5 (stating that the committee was "not
prepared to conclude categorically at this juncture" that collaborative
lawyers could not or would not give clients the information they needed
to decide whether to accept collaborative representation). The conclusions
seem to rest on a presumption in favor of allowing the CL experiment to
continue. See infra notes 155-159 and accompanying text. Unless
new studies document harms caused by collaborative representation, we are
unlikely to reach a significantly different "juncture" down the
road. RETURN TO TEXT
105.
Colo. Bar Ass'n Ethics Comm., Formal Op. 115 (Feb. 24, 2007), available
at http://www.cobar.org/group/display.cfm?GenID=10159&EntityID
=CETH. RETURN TO TEXT
106.
ABA Comm. on Ethics and Prof'l Responsibility, Formal Op. 07-447 (2007).
RETURN TO TEXT
107.
Colo. Bar Ass'n Ethics Comm., Formal Op. 115. RETURN TO TEXT
108.
Colo. Rules of Prof'l Conduct R. 1.7(b) (2007). The Colorado Supreme Court
has amended its rules of conduct, including Rule 1.7, effective January
1, 2008. Rule 1.7(b) as amended could conceivably alter the ethics committee's
conclusion, but that seems quite unlikely. Under the new version, a lawyer
may represent a client even if there is "a significant risk that the
representation will be "materially limited by the lawyer's responsibilities...
to a third person" if (b)(1) "the lawyer reasonably believes
that the lawyer will be able to provide competent and diligent representation"
and (b)(4) "the affected client gives informed consent, confirmed
in writing." What Opinion 115 describes as a material impairment of
the collaborative lawyer's ability to represent her client could just as
well be described as an inability to provide "competent and diligent
representation." RETURN TO TEXT
109.
Colo. Bar Ass'n Ethics Comm., Formal Op. 115. It seems telling that Opinion
115 refers to the spouses in divorce collaborations as "opposing parties."
RETURN TO TEXT
110.
Id. RETURN TO TEXT
111.
Id. (quoting Rule 1.7 cmt. (Loyalty to a Client)). Language
in the comments to Rule 1.7 that became effective as of January 1, 2008
is slightly different but to the same effect. See Colo. Rules Of Prof's
Conduct R. 1.7 cmt. 8 (2008) (calling the critical questions in deciding
whether a conflict is consentable "the likelihood that a difference
in interests will eventuate and, if it does, whether it will materially
interfere with the lawyer's independent professional judgment in considering
alternatives or foreclose courses of action that reasonably should be pursued
on behalf of the client") (emphasis added). RETURN TO TEXT
112.
Id. RETURN TO TEXT
113.
Id. RETURN TO TEXT
114.
In one respect, the opinion is clearly mistaken. It asserts that collaborative
lawyers are foreclosed by their role from either considering whether it
would be in their client's interest to terminate the CL process and litigate
or advising the client to do so when circumstances warrant. But collaborative
lawyers are not precluded from considering or recommending litigation,
only from litigating itself, which is no more than transactional lawyers
typically preclude by the terms of their engagement letters. See IACP Ethics
Task Force, supra note 71, at 10 (drawing the analogy to transactional
lawyers). Of course, if a transactional lawyer and his client agree at
the outset to limit their engagement to negotiating and drafting a contract,
they can later agree to drop the limitation, because they gave no third
party the right to stop them. RETURN TO TEXT
Perhaps the point is not
that collaborative lawyers are ethically or contractually foreclosed from
considering or recommending litigation, but rather that they have a pecuniary
incentive not to do so because they cannot benefit financially if the matter
goes to litigation. But biasing pecuniary incentives are endemic in law
practice. For example, personal injury lawyers working for a contingent
rather than an hourly fee may press clients to settle rather than proceed
to a trial that the lawyers consider unlikely to produce a much better
result or likely to produce a worse result. See Ted Schneyer, Legal-Process
Constraints on the Regulation of Lawyers' Contingent Fee Agreements,
47 DePaul L. Rev. 371, 389, 393-94 (1998). And adversarial divorce lawyers
paid by the hour may have a bias against recommending settlement when they
stand to gain by taking the matter to court. RETURN TO TEXT
115.
Colo. Bar Ass'n Ethics Comm., Formal Op. 115. Although the concept of cooperative
practice was used in the Colorado opinion as a point of comparison, it
is not a well-known or well-developed alternative. According to one Colorado
family law practitioner, cooperative law "is not something that anyone
in Colorado does" and none "of us knows what it is supposed to
be." See Jill Schachner Chanen, A Warning to Collaborators: Colorado
Bar Ethics Panel Takes Aim at a Growing ADR Practice, ABA J., May 2007,
available at http://abajournal.com/magazine/a_warning_to_ collaborators/.
RETURN TO TEXT
116.
Colo. Bar Ass'n Ethics Comm., Formal Op. 115, at n.11. RETURN TO TEXT
117.
Id. (calling it "axiomatic that private parties in Colorado
may contract for any legal purpose"). RETURN TO TEXT
118.
The IACP's Ethics Task Force makes the same point, calling the Colorado
opinion's focus on the fact that the CL disqualification agreement is signed
by both lawyers and both clients a "highly technical and mechanical
approach to the question" and asking how clients' interests are protected
"by such a hairsplitting view of ethics." IACP Ethics Task Force,
supra note 71, at 12 n.5. RETURN TO TEXT
119.
At the time, Colorado's conflicts rules provided, as the Model Rules do
not, that "a client's consent cannot be validly obtained in those
instances in which a disinterested lawyer would conclude that the client
should not agree to the representation," Colo. Rules Prof'l Conduct
R. 1.7(c) (2007), but Opinion 115 would clearly have reached the same conclusion
in the absence of that provision. RETURN TO TEXT
120.
ABA Comm. on Ethics and Prof'l Responsibility, Formal Op. 07-447, at 3
(2007). This is so, according to the opinion, even though comment 8 to
Model Rule 1.7 states that ""a conflict exists if there is a
significant risk that a lawyer's ability to consider, recommend, or carry
out an appropriate course of action for the client will be materially limited
by the lawyer's other responsibilities [thereby foreclosing] alternatives
that would otherwise be available to the client'." Id. at 4.
RETURN TO TEXT
121.
Id. (emphasis added). RETURN TO TEXT
122.
Id. at 4; cf. N.J. Advisory Comm. on Prof'l Ethics, Op. 699 (2005),
2005 WL 3890576, at 3 (stating that since the scope limitation "is
known at the outset" the propriety of bowing out if the process fails
to produce an agreement should be analyzed under Rule 1.2(c), not under
rules governing a lawyer's right to withdraw from an ongoing engagement).
RETURN TO TEXT
123.
ABA Comm. on Ethics and Prof'l Responsibility, Formal Op. 07-447, at 3.
A comment to Model Rule 1.2 provides that "[a] limited representation
may be appropriate because the client has limited objectives for the representation.
In addition, the terms upon which representation is undertaken may exclude
specific means that might otherwise be used to accomplish the client's
objectives." Model Rules of Prof'l Conduct R. 1.2 cmt. 6 (2007). RETURN TO TEXT
124.
When there has been a history of one spouse physically abusing the other,
for example, the risks that the abused spouse's consent will be ineffective
or that good-faith negotiations will be impossible are likely to make CL
an unreasonable alternative. For a discussion of circumstances in which
spouses are likely and unlikely to be good candidates for CL, see Tesler,
supra note 4, at 94-95. RETURN TO TEXT
125.
ABA Comm. on Ethics and Prof'l Responsibility, Formal Op. 07-447, at 3.
RETURN TO TEXT
126.
In its critique of Colorado Opinion 115, the IACP Ethics Task Force calls
the opinion a "maverick." IACP Ethics Task Force, supra
note 71. For evidence of the ABA ethics committee's substantial influence
on the opinions of state and local bar association opinions, see Finman
& Schneyer, supra note 93, at 82-83 & nn.62-65. RETURN TO TEXT
127.
E.g., ABA Comm. on Ethics and Prof'l Responsibility, Formal Op.
07-447, at 2 (stating that informed consent requires the lawyer to communicate
"adequate information and explanation about the material risks and
reasonably available alternatives to the limited representation [and] about
the rules or contractual terms governing the collaborative process, [and
to] ensure that the client understands that if the process does not result
in a settlement and litigation is the only recourse, the lawyer "must
withdraw and the parties must retain new lawyers to prepare the matter
for trial"). RETURN TO TEXT
128.
Indeed, Tesler's discussion of client screening, Tesler, supra note
4, at 94-95, offers more helpful guidance than any of the mainstream opinions.
But see N.J. Advisory Comm. on Prof'l Ethics, Op. 699 (2005), 2005 WL 3890576,
at 4 (stating that, in view of the "particular potential for hardship
to both clients" if the CL process should fail, it is not reasonable
to accept a limited-scope CL engagement "if the lawyer, based on her
knowledge and experience and after being fully informed about the existing
relationship between the parties, believes that there is a significant
possibility that an impasse will result or the collaborative process will
otherwise fail"). This screening standard is not as constraining as
it may seem, because anecdotal evidence suggests that 95% of divorce collaborations
do result in settlement agreements. See supra note 21. For further
discussion of the treatment of client screening in the New Jersey opinion,
See infra note 141. RETURN TO TEXT
129.
The opinion does resort to adversarial rhetoric, however, by calling the
spouses in a CL proceeding "opposing parties," see supra
note 112 and accompanying text, even though the spouses commit themselves
at the outset to pursue "a negotiated agreement that meets the legitimate
needs of both parties." See supra note 25 and accompanying
text. Tesler discourages collaborative lawyers from describing their client's
spouse as an "opposing party" rather than the "other"
spouse. Tesler, supra note 4, at 57. RETURN TO TEXT
130.
I have argued elsewhere that the prevailing rules of legal ethics are not
dominated by any overarching theory or "paradigm" but instead
reflect multiple conceptions of the lawyer's role vying rather inconclusively
for dominance in professional debate. Ted Schneyer, Moral Philosophy's
Standard Misconception of Legal Ethics, 1984 Wis. L. Rev. 1529, 1550-56,
1564-69. This, of course, is not to deny that today's legal culture motivates
some litigators to act like "junkyard dogs" or that the prevailing
rules may give undue attention to litigation ethics. RETURN TO TEXT
131.
Model Code of Prof'l Responsibility Canon 7 (1969). RETURN TO TEXT
132.
See Lande, supra note 74, at 1332, 1384 nn.52-54. RETURN TO TEXT
133.
E.g., Model Rules of Prof'l Conduct R. 1.3 cmt. 1 (stating that
a lawyer is "not bound ... to press for every advantage that might
be realized for a client"); cf. Restatement (Third) of the Law Governing
Lawyers § 16 cmt. d (2000) (stating that although zealous advocacy
is a "traditional aspiration" for lawyers, "it should not
be misunderstood to suggest that lawyers are legally required to function
with a certain emotion or style of litigating, negotiating or counseling
[and that, f]or legal purposes, the term encompasses [nothing more than]
the duties of competence and diligence"). RETURN TO TEXT
134.
Lande, supra note 74, at 1333 n.57 (quoting the Academy's Bounds
of Advocacy as revised in 2000). RETURN TO TEXT
135.
More precisely, the lawyer may propose a limitation on the scope or objectives
and may decline an engagement if the prospective client disagrees, but
may not limit the scope or objectives without the client's approval. RETURN TO TEXT
136.
E.g., Model Rules of Prof'l Conduct R. 1.9(a) (forbidding a lawyer
to represent a client against a former client in a substantially related
matter without obtaining the former client's consent, but treating the
informed consent of both as sufficient to permit the new representation
-- whatever the risk that the lawyer will use confidential information
gained from the former client against him). RETURN TO TEXT
137.
E.g., id. at R. 1.5(d)(2) (forbidding criminal defense lawyers
to charge contingent fee even if a client proposes it, because such fees
can adversely affect a lawyer's advice about whether to accept a plea bargain);
R. 4.2 (forbidding a lawyer who represents a client to communicate about
the matter with a person the lawyer knows is also represented in the matter,
unless the lawyer obtains the consent of that person's lawyer -- even if
the person is willing to waive the protection the rule affords him). See
generally David Luban, Paternalism and the Legal Profession, 1981 Wis.
L. Rev. 454. RETURN TO TEXT
138.
E.g., Model Rules of Prof'l Conduct R. 1.2(c) (permitting limitations
on the scope of representation if the client gives informed consent, but
only if the limitation is "reasonable under the circumstances");
R. 1.7(a)(2), (b)(1) (permitting a lawyer who obtains the informed consent
to represent the client, even if there is a "significant risk that
the representation [will be] materially limited by the lawyer's responsibilities
to... a third person or by a personal interest of the lawyer" but
only if "the lawyer reasonably believes that [he or she] will be able
to provide competent and diligent representation"). RETURN TO TEXT
139.
The Colorado opinion relied on Rule 1.7 of the Colorado Rules of Professional
Conduct, not Model Rule 1.7, but for present purposes the two are not significantly
different. This Article generally refers to the Model Rules since they
are the best evidence of the prevailing rules of legal ethics today. RETURN TO TEXT
140.
See supra note 138. RETURN TO TEXT
141.
The New Jersey opinion is equivocal on whether most potential CL engagements
can pass muster. See supra note 127. Presumably, however, careful
screening of potential clients will weed out engagements in which a collaborative
lawyer believes there is a "significant possibility" of failure.
Although the opinion finds it "easy to imagine" situations in
which a collaborative lawyer would be inclined to describe the risks and
benefits of the process in a way that promotes an engagement "even
if the client's interests might be better served by" traditional divorce
representation, the drafters were "not prepared" to conclude
that the lawyer "would be unable to deal with those conflicts honorably,
or could not give the client the information necessary" to make an
informed choice. N.J. Advisory Comm. on Prof'l Ethics, Op. 699, 2005 WL
3890576, at 5. RETURN TO TEXT
142.
In comparing the policy merits of the balance struck in the Colorado and
ABA opinions, it would be a mistake to focus solely on the risks that CL
poses for clients. Other things being equal, spouses who choose court-based
divorce presumably run the greater risk of harming themselves and their
children in bitter litigation or rancorous negotiations. CL clients presumably
bind themselves by a mutual commitment to good faith negotiation in hopes
of reducing the risk that they will cause such harm, just as Ulysses had
his crew tie him to the mast so he would not succumb to the Sirens' call
and have his ship founder. See Jeffrey W. Stempel, Ulysses Tied to the
Generic Whipping Post: The Continuing Odyssey of Discovery Reform,
64 Law & Contemp. Probs. 197, 200 n.16 (2001) (noting that "the
Ulysses metaphor" has become popular in legal literature "because
it so well captures the role of rules in limiting discretion as a means
of saving decisionmakers from potential error"). RETURN TO TEXT
143.
Large law firms began to form ancillary businesses, such as lobbying or
environmental consulting firms, in the 1980s. In those firms, unlike law
firms, allied professionals could join lawyers as principals. In 1991,
however, the ABA adopted a Model Rule barring lawyers and law firms from
owning and operating ancillary businesses. See Ted Schneyer, Policymaking
and the Perils of Professionalism: The ABA's Ancillary Business Debate
as a Case Study, 35 Ariz. L. Rev. 363, 364 (1993). The ABA Litigation
Section, which pressed for the ban, produced no evidence that the existing
ancillary businesses were harming clients. It supported the ban instead
by raising highly speculative concerns, including a perceived need to protect
clients from (1) the risk that when law firms referred their clients to
law-related service providers they would recommend their own ancillary
businesses even if other providers were more appropriate, (2) the risk
that clients served by a law firm's ancillary business would be confused
about whether or when they were entitled to all the ethical protections
afforded clients in traditional lawyer-client relationships, and (3) the
risk that an ancillary's non-lawyer principals would interfere with the
lawyers' exercise of independent judgment on behalf of their clients. Id.
at 375-77. One leader in the Litigation Section conceded that a risk the
section associated with ancillary businesses was only speculative, but
argued that "the only relevant question is whether the profession
is willing to take that indeterminable risk." Id. at 372-73
(quoting Lawrence J. Fox).
However, the mainstream
bar's historical tendency to ban new or heterodox practice arrangements
for the sake of protecting clients from speculative risks was dealt a blow
in 1992, when the ancillary business ban was dropped. Proponents of repeal
produced evidence that the new ancillary businesses were serving clients
well, id. at 387, and called on the ABA to forbear, in the absence of evidence
of harm, from declaring any particular form of practice unethical. Id.
at 370, 386-87. RETURN TO TEXT
144.
See Bates v. State Bar of Arizona, 433 U.S. 350, 368, 372-75 (1977)
(striking down on First Amendment grounds ethics rules banning lawyer advertising,
rules that had long been criticized by consumer advocates). RETURN TO TEXT
145.
For an account of the ABA's slow and grudging abandonment of its ethical
ban on lawyer participation in group and prepaid legal services plans in
the wake of Supreme Court decisions protecting such plans on First Amendment
grounds, see Vern Countryman, Ted Finman & Theodore J. Schneyer, The
Lawyer in Modern Society 620-25 (2d ed. 1976). Whether the former ABA bans
on lawyer advertising, participation in group legal services plans, and
ownership and operation of ancillary businesses were truly motivated by
paternalism or, rather, by economic protectionism dressed up in paternalistic
rhetoric is, of course, debatable. See Schneyer, supra note 143,
at 390-91. RETURN TO TEXT
146.
Model Rules of Prof'l Conduct R. 1.7 cmt.[22] provides that "if the
client... consents to a particular type of conflict with which the client
is already familiar, then the consent will ordinarily be effective [and]
if the client is an experienced user of the legal services involved and
is reasonably informed regarding the risk that a conflict may arise, such
consent is more likely to be effective, particularly if, E.g., the
client is independently represented by other counsel in giving consent
and the consent is limited to future conflicts unrelated to the subject
of the representation." If the matters are unrelated, the risk is
low that the lawyer will receive confidential client information in one
that he can use against the client in the other. The sophisticated client
par excellence is a corporation whose general counsel decides whether to
give an advance waiver of conflicts when retaining an outside law firm.
For discussion of the evolving treatment of advance waivers of conflicts
in the Model Rules, see Ronald D. Rotunda & John S. Dzienkowski, Professional
Responsibility: A Student's Guide § 1.7-4(b) (2006-07). RETURN TO TEXT
147.
Restatement (Third) of the Law Governing Lawyers § 34 cmt. c (2000)
(identifying client sophistication or experience in retaining lawyers as
a factor in favor of upholding a fee agreement that is challenged in a
contract action or disciplinary proceeding on the ground that the fee is
unreasonably high). RETURN TO TEXT
148.
See, E.g., Richard W. Painter, Game Theoretic and Contractarian
Paradigms in the Uneasy Relationship Between Regulators and Regulatory
Lawyers, 65 Fordham L. Rev. 149 (1996); Peppet, supra note 3;
Larry E. Ribstein, Ethical Rules, Agency Costs, and Law Firm Structure,
84 Va. L. Rev. 1707, 1751-58 (1998); William H. Simon, Who Needs the
Bar?: Professionalism Without Monopoly, 30 Fla. St. U. L. Rev. 639,
654-55 (2003). RETURN TO TEXT
149.
N.J. Advisory Comm. on Prof'l Ethics, Op. 699 (2005), 2005 WL 3890576,
at 5. Tesler concurs, but adds that collaborative lawyers are strongly
motivated to obtain "super informed consent," so that clients
can later be reminded, if necessary, that they received clear and complete
information about the potential risks and advantages of CL compared to
the alternatives before opting for CL. Telephone Interview with Pauline
Tesler, supra note 10. RETURN TO TEXT
150.
Model Rules of Prof'l Conduct R. 2.1 cmt. 5. RETURN TO TEXT
151.
It would be interesting to know how the percentage of exclusively "adversarial"
divorce lawyers who fairly present the CL alternative to their prospective
clients compares with the percentage of exclusively collaborative lawyers
who fairly present the litigation alternative to theirs. Lawyers who offer
both forms of representation can probably be relied upon most to present
the alternatives objectively. See supra note 75. RETURN TO TEXT
152.
See John Lande, Lessons for Collaborative Lawyers and Other Dispute
Resolution Professionals from Colorado Bar Association Ethics Opinion 115,
Mediate.com, Apr. 2007, http://mediate.com/articles/landeJ3.cfm (faulting
the opinion's "categorical findings" for being "unsupported
by any evidence of actual problems"). RETURN TO TEXT
153.
Professor Macfarlane's study, based chiefly on interviews of collaborative
lawyers and clients in several U.S. and Canadian cities from 2001 to 2003,
Macfarlane, supra note 7, at 187-88, remains the only substantial
empirical examination of CL. She found it too early to say whether CL poses
serious ethical problems, id. at 211, but found evidence that CL
"can bring good results to many family clients." Id. at
216. More research will be needed in order to make informed judgments about
the nature and magnitude of CL's risks and benefits. RETURN TO TEXT
154.
Philosopher Alasdair MacIntyre argues that longstanding communities, including
professional communities, have "dynamic" rather than static traditions
and maintain cohesion through ongoing debate about the meaning of those
traditions under new circumstances. See Jean Porter, Tradition
in the Recent Work of Alasdair MacIntyre, in Alasdair MacIntyre 38,
39-40 (Mark Murphy ed. 2003) (discussing MacIntyre's treatment of tradition);
see also Lisa H. Newton, Lawgiving for Professional Life: Reflections
on the Place of the Professional Code, 1 Bus. & Prof'l Ethics 41
(Fall 1981) (stating that "articulation of the professional ethic
is what makes a profession a moral enterprise"); Schneyer, supra
note 86, at 96 (describing the six-year political process in which the
ABA produced the Model Rules in a time of professional turmoil as a "sustained
and democratic debate about professional ethics"). RETURN TO TEXT
155.
Lande, supra note 152. RETURN TO TEXT
156.
See supra note 143. RETURN TO TEXT
157.
See supra notes 127 and 141. RETURN TO TEXT
158.
See supra note 104. RETURN TO TEXT
159.
See supra text accompanying note 149. RETURN TO TEXT
160.
Using a list of 41 narrowly defined practice fields and surveying a
large sample of Chicago lawyers in 1995, researchers at the American Bar
Foundation determined that fully one-third of the respondents confined
their practice to one of those fields and that the percentage had risen
significantly since 1975. John P. Heinz et al., Urban Lawyers: The
New Social Structure of the Bar 37 (2005). One might even call the trend
"hyper-specialization." As Professor Tom Morgan puts it, some
lawyers now limit their practice not just to plaintiff's personal injury
work, or products liability cases, or cases involving pharmaceutical products,
but cases involving a single drug such as Vioxx. Thomas D. Morgan, Educating
Lawyers for the Future Legal Profession, 30 Okla. City. U. L. Rev.
537, 545 (2005). RETURN TO TEXT
161.
See Milton C. Regan, Jr., Eat What You Kill: The Fall of a Wall
Street Lawyer 8 (2004) (arguing that sizable law firms are now divided
into practice groups defined largely by specialty field and "as a
result, lawyers [in those firms] draw many of their norms and much of their
practice culture from colleagues working in the same specialty, rather
than from the firm as a whole"). RETURN TO TEXT
162.
See supra note 9. RETURN TO TEXT
163.
Conflict was minimal when the ABA drafted the Canons of Professional Ethics
in the 1900s, but professional fault lines were quite evident when the
ABA drafted the Model Rules in the late 1970s and early 1980s. See
Schneyer, supra note 78, at 564-65 & nn.21-23. RETURN TO TEXT
164.
Schneyer, supra note 86, at 97 (using the term "ethical
pluralism" to refer to the growing range of ethical outlooks that
exist within the legal profession and suggesting that greater variation
in outlook is correlated with increasing specialization in practice, growth
in specialty bar associations, and greater segmentation of the legal services
market). Here, I give the term the further connotation of increasing willingness
of lawyers to tolerate variations in ethical outlook and accept the proliferation
of specialized guidelines for practice specific fields. RETURN TO TEXT
165.
Some "adversarial" divorce lawyers and family mediators may fear
competition for clients from collaborative lawyers. See Macfarlane, supra
note 7, at 212, 214-16 (citing evidence of business rivalry between collaborative
lawyers and family mediators). RETURN TO TEXT
166.
E.g., Collaborative Family Law Agreement, available at www.abanet.org/?family/?mo/premium-fl/orc/collab/CollaborativeFamLawAgreement, Col
RETURN TO TEXT
167.
Tesler, supra note 4. RETURN TO TEXT
168.
See Lawyer as Problem-Solver Award, Just Resolutions (ABA Sec. of Disp.
Resol.), Oct. 2002, at 3. Webb first conceived of CL. RETURN TO TEXT
169.
Section of Dispute Resolution: Collaborative Law Comm., Mission and Committee
Meetings, available at http://www.abanet.org/dch/?committee.cfm??com=DR035000
(last visited Oct. 7, 2007) (emphasis added). As of October 2007, the committee
had 62 members. Id. However, ABA entities are not unanimous in supporting
CL. The ABA General Practice, Solo and Small Firm Division has published
an article highly critical of CL. See Karen A. Rose & Jonathan
W. Wolfe, Collaborative Law -- The Potential Downside of the Latest Trend
in Marital Dissolution, GP/Solo Law Trends & News (Family Law), May
2005, available at http://www.abanet.org/?genpractice/newsletter/?lawtrends/?0506/
family/collaborativelaw.html (arguing that most divorcing couples cannot
be expected "to put [angry] feelings aside and enter into a cooperative
negotiation process," that the disqualification agreement is "coercive,"
that "collaborative theorists conveniently overlook the fact that
sometimes negotiations should break down," that the collaborative
lawyer's "refusal to follow orders from irrational clients" is
problematic, and that "one can imagine a situation where the party
with greater financial assets enters into the collaborative process in
order to take advantage of informal discovery practices and then refuses
to negotiate in good faith"). RETURN TO TEXT
170.
The mainstream ethics opinions on the subject, discussed above, provide
some guidance on what a lawyer must tell a prospective client in order
to obtain her informed consent to a limited scope CL engagement, less guidance
on the prospective clients for whom CL representation would be appropriate,
and almost none on the other issues they mention. See, e.g., Pa.
Bar Ass'n Comm. on Legal Ethics & Prof'l Responsibility, Informal Op.
2004-24 (2004), 2004 WL 2758094, at 7 (questioning whether the limited
scope of CL representation is compatible with a lawyer's unwaivable duty
of competence, calling this "one of the most difficult issues presented
by collaborative law," and noting that CL's scope limitation essentially
waives a client's right to use formal discovery or subpoena witnesses to
gather information, but leaving it to the lawyer to consider in each client's
case whether those waivers are consistent with the duty of competence).
RETURN TO TEXT
171.
See Charles W. Wolfram, Modern Legal Ethics 713 (1986) (stating that
legal ethics codes "in most respects leave negotiating lawyers on
the same legal and regulatory plane as their clients"). Professor
Wolfram also notes that "professional restraints on lawyers as negotiators
have tended toward the minimal." Id. at 714. The Model Rules
contain many rules governing lawyers as advocates, Model Rules of Prof'l
Conduct R. 3.1-3.9 (2007), but only one rule written chiefly with negotiation
in mind, and that rule is not ethically ambitious. Compare id. at R. 4.1
(providing that in representing a client a lawyer shall not knowingly "(a)
make a false statement of material fact or law to a third person; or (b)
fail to disclose a material fact when disclosure is necessary to avoid
assisting a criminal or fraudulent act by a client, unless disclosure is
prohibited" by the lawyer's duty of confidentiality), with id.
at R. 4.1 cmt. 2 (treating as immaterial most "estimates of price
or value on the subject of a transaction and [statements about] a party's
intentions as to an acceptable settlement"). Cf. ABA Section
of Litigation, Ethical Guidelines for Settlement Negotiations (Aug. 2002),
in Professional Standards, Rules & Statutes 976 (John S. Dzienkowski
ed. 2007-08) (offering guidelines for litigators conducting settlement
negotiations, but noting that the guidelines are only aspirational and
not intended to preempt the Model Rules). RETURN TO TEXT
172.
Representing clients in settling legal disputes is the practice of law
and nonlawyers can be enjoined from doing so on the ground that it constitutes
the unauthorized practice of law. See, e.g., Professional Adjusters,
Inc. v. Tandon, 433 N.E.2d 779 (Ind. 1982) (holding that lay "adjusters"
who contracted to negotiate a settlement of clients' claim against their
own insurance company were engaged in the unauthorized practice of law).
RETURN TO TEXT
173.
See, E.g., Wolfram, supra note 171, at 714 (arguing that
if professional rules hobbled lawyer-negotiators in ways that clients and
lay negotiating agents are not hobbled, "a well-advised client"
would either negotiate on his own or "hire negotiators who are not
lawyers"). Scott Peppet offers the rival hypothesis that ethical norms
governing lawyer-negotiators are weak because the rule makers regard negotiation
chiefly as a prelude to litigation and will not impose more demanding duties
to third parties in negotiations than lawyers owe to opposing parties in
litigation. Peppet, supra note 3, at 479-80. RETURN TO TEXT
174.
For a rich account of the "private legal system" that the cotton
industry has developed over time to govern business relations within the
industry, see Lisa Bernstein, Private Commercial Law in the Cotton Industry:
Creating Cooperation Through Rules, Norms, and Institutions, 99 Mich.
L. Rev. 1724 (2001). Bernstein's account led me to think of the developing
infrastructure that supports the CL process as a private legal system.
RETURN TO TEXT
175.
For a lucid overview of game theory and its application in law and policy
analysis, see Douglas G. Baird, Robert H. Gertner & Randal C. Picker,
Game Theory and the Law (1994). RETURN TO TEXT
176.
This is a variation on a hypothetical posed by Scott Peppet in an article
on lawyers' bargaining ethics. Peppet, supra note 3, at 478. For
simplicity, I assume that no malpractice insurer is involved. RETURN TO TEXT
177.
Id. at 483 (quoting William H. Simon, The Practice of Justice: A
Theory of Lawyers Ethics 209 (1998)). This problem, commonly referred to
in game theory as "the prisoner's dilemma," tends to be less
serious if the parties had prior dealings and hope to maintain a good relationship
in the future. Divorcing couples have of course had a prior relationship,
but may find it very hard to trust one another at the time of divorce and
may be uncertain about the importance of maintaining a post-divorce RETURN TO TEXTrelationship.
RETURN TO TEXT
178.
See Ronald J. Gilson & Robert H. Mnookin, Disputing Through
Agents: Cooperation and Conflict Between Lawyers, 94 Colum. L. Rev.
509, 550-57 (1994). RETURN TO TEXT
179.
See Peppet, supra note 3, at 478. RETURN TO TEXT
180.
Id. RETURN TO TEXT
181.
See Simon, supra note 148, at 655-56 RETURN TO TEXT
182.
See supra note 171. RETURN TO TEXT
183.
See Peppet, supra note 3, at 479-80. RETURN TO TEXT
184.
See, e.g., Texas Collaborative Law Council, Inc., Protocols of Practice
for Collaborative Lawyers § 2.01 cmt. (rev. Aug. 2007), available
at http://collaborativelaw.us/?news.php (explaining the difference
between CL and handling a case on a "settlement track" with litigation
looming in the background). The IACP has circulated an "adapted"
version of the Texas protocols for comment and intends them as "a
guideline for use by licensed attorneys and other licensed professionals
who are trained in the collaborative dispute resolution process."
IACP, Protocols of Practice for Civil Collaborative Lawyers (Oct. 13. 2006).
RETURN TO TEXT
185.
Such information would obviously include adverse facts that might not be
subject to discovery. This may explain why clients occasionally retain
two lawyers at the outset, one as "settlement counsel," the other
to prepare for litigation. See Robert Fisher, What About Negotiation
as a Specialty?, 69 A.B.A. J. 1221 (1983). RETURN TO TEXT
186.
See supra note 25 and accompanying text. RETURN TO TEXT
187.
Even more than the strangers in the medical malpractice hypothetical discussed
in this section, divorcing spouses often have reason to distrust one another,
but unlike strangers, each knows the other well enough to judge whether
he or she can be trusted in collaborative negotiations. RETURN TO TEXT
188.
I borrow the term "chaperone" from Reinier Kraakman, who uses
it to describe the role of corporate "gatekeepers" such as auditors.
"Chaperone" gatekeepers, while providing a service to their clients,
also monitor the clients for the benefit of regulatory agencies or the
investing public and are expected to withhold their approval or assistance
if they detect wrongdoing. Kraakman, supra note 58, at 64. But,
while public corporations are required to retain auditors to supply information
for the benefit of the investing public, a spouse who retains a collaborative
lawyer as a "chaperone" who can "certify" the spouse's
good faith to the other side freely chooses to do so in hopes of achieving
her goals through collaboration. RETURN TO TEXT
189.
Law-and-economics scholars describe a lawyer who puts this asset at stake
as "posting a reputational bond." See, e.g., Ribstein,
supra note 148, at 1709-14, 1739-40. Although law firms cultivate
good reputations (a form of "branding"), it is unclear how much
a firm's reputation "says" to others about what can be expected
of any particular lawyer in the firm. RETURN TO TEXT
190.
See supra notes 10-11. RETURN TO TEXT
191.
See supra notes 10-11. RETURN TO TEXT
192.
In 1936, the ABA was reorganized in part as a federation. Policymaking
authority was vested in the House of Delegates, in which state and some
local bar associations have direct representation. See Hurst, supra
note 9, at 290-92. RETURN TO TEXT
193.
See Welcome to New IACP Whole Group Memberships, Collaborative Connection,
Feb. 2007, available at http://collaborativepractice.com/newsgen.asp??ID=2143595669.
RETURN TO TEXT
194.
See Tesler, supra note 4, at 173 n.3. The selective membership
policies are reminiscent of the initial policies of many bar associations
formed in the late 1800s and early 1900s, after decades in which bar admission
standards had been minimal. Those policies produced cohesion within the
associations but limited the bar's influence in public debates. See
Hurst, supra note 9, at 288. RETURN TO TEXT
195.
See Tesler, supra note 4, at 174, 176. RETURN TO TEXT
196.
See id. at 172. RETURN TO TEXT
197.
See id. at 174, 176. RETURN TO TEXT
198.
See id. at 175 (listing a local practice group's membership requirements).
RETURN TO TEXT
199.
See Lynda Robbins, Use of the Collaborative Practice "C"
Mark, Collaborative Connection, Nov. 2006, available at http://collaborativepractice.com/?newsgen.asp??ID=1164648380.
RETURN TO TEXT
200.
See Collaborative Connection, Mar. 2007, at http://collaborativepractice.com/?t2.asp?T=Ethics.
RETURN TO TEXT
201.
The ABA has developed voluntary standards for lawyers mediating family
disputes, but not for lay mediators. ABA Standards of Practice for Lawyer
Mediators in Family Disputes (1984). RETURN TO TEXT
202.
IACP Ethics Task Force, supra note 71. RETURN TO TEXT
203.
Collaborative Connection, supra note 197. RETURN TO TEXT
204.
IACP Ethical Standards for Collaborative Practitioners (rev. Jan. 2007),
Collaborative Connection, Mar. 2007, available at http://collaborativepractice.com/?newsgen.asp??ID=165222305.
RETURN TO TEXT
205.
See id. RETURN TO TEXT
206.
This is surely one reason why CL has taken root in family law practice
but not in other fields. RETURN TO TEXT
207.
Tesler's manual provides useful guidance on client screening. Tesler, supra
note 4, at 94-95. Moreover, some CL practice groups have developed protocols
for client screening. See, e.g., Texas Collaborative Law Council,
Inc., supra note 184, sec. 2.02. RETURN TO TEXT
208.
Hurst, supra note 9, at 286. Although Hurst is not speaking specifically
of formal bar organizations, new bar associations were mushrooming at the
time and the profession was becoming more heterogeneous. Bar leaders stressed
the growing importance of the associations' socialization and disciplinary
functions in promoting ethical practice and in establishing and maintaining
lawyers' reputations. See, e.g., Julius Henry Cohen, The Law: Business
or Profession 199, 333 (rev. ed. 1924). Cohen's ideas about the value of
professional associations closely parallel those of his contemporary, French
sociologist Emile Durkheim. See Emile Durkheim, Professional Ethics
and Civic Morals 5-14 (1958). RETURN TO TEXT
209.
Tesler, supra note 4, at 173 n.3. RETURN TO TEXT
210.
Macfarlane, supra note 7, at 196. RETURN TO TEXT
211.
N.J. Advisory Comm. on Prof'l Ethics, Op. 699 (2005), 2005 WL 3890576,
at 2; see also N.C. Formal Eth. Op. 1 (2002) (same). RETURN TO TEXT
212.
See supra note 24 and accompanying text. RETURN TO TEXT
213.
See supra note 204 and accompanying text. RETURN TO TEXT
214.
See supra note 184. RETURN TO TEXT
215.
Macfarlane, supra note 7, at 196. RETURN TO TEXT
216.
Texas Collaborative Law Council, Inc., Protocols of Practice for Collaborative
Lawyers, supra note 184, at sec. 1.03. Discipline would probably
be limited, except in extraordinary cases, to admonitions or censure, but
just as importantly, a member's serious or recurring misconduct would quickly
become known to other members who might become reluctant to collaborate
with her, or more cautious in doing so, in the future. RETURN TO TEXT
217.
See Tesler, supra note 4, at 174 n.4. RETURN TO TEXT
218.
This devolution was foretold in an incident that occurred in the 1980s
as the Model Rules were being drafted. The American Trial Lawyer's Association
("ATLA"), believing that the ABA drafting commission was (from
a trial lawyer's standpoint) insufficiently committed to the traditional
ethical values of confidentiality and zealous advocacy, tried to unseat
the ABA as the law giver for the profession by drafting a rival code for
state adoption. When the chair of the ABA commission protested that ATLA,
as a specialty bar, was ill-suited to write a code for all lawyers, he
was publicly chided by an ATLA leader for presuming that the states would
"bow down before the infallible pope of legal ethics and adopt what
the [the ABA] says ought to be the rules." See Ted Schneyer, Professionalism
as Bar Politics: The Making of the Model Rules of Professional Conduct,
14 Law & Soc. Inquiry 677, 711 (1989) (quoting ATLA's Thomas Lumbard).
RETURN TO TEXT
219.
See supra note 87. RETURN TO TEXT
220.
See Schneyer, supra note 78, at 562-63 & n.16; see
also Murray L. Schwartz, The Death and Regeneration of Ethics,
1980 Am. B. Found Res. J. 953, 954 (1980) (predicting a proliferation of
practice guidelines for specialty fields in the wake of ABA adoption of
the Model Rules). RETURN TO TEXT
221.
See supra notes 92-93 and accompanying text. RETURN TO TEXT
222.
See supra notes 104, 141, 157-158 and accompanying text. RETURN TO TEXT
223.
See supra text accompanying notes 209-211. Moreover, while the
ABA formulates ethics codes for adoption at the state level, a top down
approach, CL's local and regional practice groups often develop practice
guidelines that are then adapted and disseminated by the IACP, a bottom-up
approach. See supra note 184. RETURN TO TEXT
224.
See supra notes 160-164 and accompanying text. Specialization also
increases the influence of specialty bar "sections" in the governance
of mainstream bar associations. See Schneyer, supra note
78, at 563-64. RETURN TO TEXT
225.
See Schneyer, supra note 218, at 691. RETURN TO TEXT
226.
See Schwartz, supra note 220, at 954 (explaining how legally
unenforceable specialty guidelines may nonetheless have considerable influence.)
RETURN TO TEXT
227.
See supra notes 157-159 and accompanying text. RETURN TO TEXT
228.
William H. Simon, Introduction: The Post-Enron Identity Crisis of the
Business Lawyer, 74 Fordham L. Rev. 947, 951 (2005). RETURN TO TEXT
229.
Id. RETURN TO TEXT
230.
For a rich discussion of this topic, see W. Wesley Pue, Death Squads and
"Directions Over Lunch": A Comparative Review of the Independence
of the Bar, available at http://ssrn.com/abstract=1000725. RETURN TO TEXT